Stephen Kershnar
The Constitution
Does Not Protect Fetuses
Dunkirk-Fredonia
Observer
November 29, 2021
This Wednesday, the Supreme Court
will hear Dobbs v. Jackson Women’s Health Organization concerning
Mississippi’s abortion law.
Mississippi banned abortions
performed after the first 15 weeks of pregnancy. The law does not permit
abortion in the case of rape or incest but permits it when there is a medical
emergency or severe fetal abnormality. The 15-week period is odd. A fetus begins
to have a heartbeat after 6 weeks, forms a
brain after 6 weeks, and – on one
influential account - does not become conscious until 24 weeks. It is unclear
what happens at 15 weeks.
Other states have also passed other pro-life
laws. The Texas Heartbeat
Act
prevents abortions after fetal heartbeat, which usually occurs 6 weeks after
conception. Georgia banned abortions after 6
weeks. The three states’ laws conflict with Roe v. Wade (1973), a landmark
Supreme Court case that held that a woman has a right to an abortion up to 24
weeks because fetuses up to that time are not viable. A fetus is viable when it
can survive outside the womb.
One issue is whether the
Constitution protects fetuses. There are two provisions that someone might
think protects the fetus. The Due Process Clause says, “[No state shall] deprive any person
of life, liberty, or property, without due process of law.” The Equal
Protection Clause says, “[No state shall] deny to any person within its
jurisdiction the equal protection of the laws.” Emphasis added. The issue here
is in part whether “person” refers to fetuses. Oxford University’s C’Zar
Bernstein argues that the Due Process Clause is less relevant because, in
the context of abortion, the life-takers are private citizens rather than the
state. He also notes that the argument over abortion does not concern procedure.
The most
plausible way to way to interpret the Constitution involves originalism.
Originalism asserts that the meaning of a Constitutional provision was set at
the time it was passed. The idea is that Constitutional provisions have
meaning, and this meaning persists over time. This can occur only if the
meaning is set when it was originally passed. On different interpretations, the
meaning of a provision is fixed by the authors’ or ratifiers’ intention, the
ordinary meaning of the language to the public when it was passed, or its
inherited common-law meaning. On this last view, the law incorporated the
common law – specifically, English-judge-made law – because it used common-law
words and phrases.
The
meaning of “person” should be understood in common law terms because it – along
with other terms such as “cruel
and unusual punishment” – was intended and
understood to be a term of art, that is, a word whose meaning tracked specific
legal meaning rather than ordinary meaning. One reason for this is that the
Constitution’s authors and ratifiers thought about and wrote the Constitution with
common-law meanings in mind. Another reason for this is the way in which language
works in specialized fields. Consider, for example, how commerce, science, and
sport use terms of art.
Bernstein
argues that the common law set the meaning of person according to the Born
Alive Rule. This rule states that a human being becomes a person only after
live birth. This can be seen in English common law regarding homicide (homicide
applied only to the killing of a born human being), tort law (no liability for
pre-natal injury), and inheritance (a human being may inherit only if he is
born). This matters because the 14th Amendment’s Due Process and the
Equal Protection clauses used some of the same language as the 5th
Amendment’s Due Process Clause, language that came from the British common law.
If this
common law interpretation is correct, then the Constitutional term, “person,”
does not refer to a fetus. It still might be the case that as a matter of
constitutional law, states have a compelling interest in protecting fetal life
and that the ban on abortion is a necessary means by which to do this, but this
involves the sort of moral reasoning that originalists hesitate to engage in.
Consider
the moral debate over abortion. It comes down to three issues. (1) Is the fetus
a person in the metaphysical sense? That is, were we ever fetuses? (2) Does the
fetus have a moral right to inside the woman? (3) If the fetus does not have a
right to be inside the woman, may the woman kill it as a way of protecting her body
against invasion? That is, is an unwanted pregnancy a body-invasion similar to
a rape? These philosophical issues are outside of the Supreme Court’s expertise
and ones that it botched in the past. Perhaps the court must address these
issues in deciding what the Equal Protection Clause means, but then it seems to
blur the distinction between interpreting and making law. That is, addressing
(1) to (3) appears to be legislating.
If the
common-law interpretation is correct, then professors – for example, Oxford
University’s John Finnis – who argue that the Constitution requires that abortion be made
illegal because the Constitution protects “persons” - are mistaken because
fetuses are not Constitutional persons. In addition, if the common-law
interpretation is correct, then the Justices should be wary of putting too much
weight on precedent - especially Roe
v. Wade (1973) and Planned
Parenthood v. Casey (1992) - because the
Court decided these decisions without acknowledging that a fetus is not a
Constitutional person and because it did not show its moral reasoning,
particularly with regard to issues (1) to (3). In addition, its focus on
viability is best seen as a political compromise rather than a good faith
attempt to interpret the Constitution.
Instead, the
Court should do one of two things. It should engage in explicit moral reasoning
regarding women’s and fetuses’ rights. Alternatively, it should declare that such
reasoning is legislating and hold that Constitution does not address the issue.
The issue would then get kicked back to the states.
No comments:
Post a Comment