Stephen Kershnar
University Vaccine
Mandates
Dunkirk Fredonia
Observer
October 11, 2021
Many American universities have Covid-vaccine
mandate. There are two purported justifications for government schools requiring
students get vaccinated. First, they want to prevent the unvaccinated from
harming themselves. Second, they want to prevent the unvaccinated from harming other
people.
Consider whether we should pressure college
students in order to protect them against harming themselves. As George Mason
economist Bryan Caplan points out Covid poses
little danger to them. The Covid infection fatality
rate
(death rate per infection) for college age students (specifically,
25-year-olds) is 0.01% (1 in 10,000). If
the college student is vaccinated, his infection fatality
rate
is 90% lower. The rate is now 0.001%
(1 in 100,000). So far one in three Americans have
gotten Covid. So, the numbers should be discounted by the chance that the
student does not get Covid. Let us arbitrarily set this at 33%. Crudely, then,
the chance of death by Covid, then, is 0.003% (3 in 100,000) for the
unvaccinated student and 0.0003% (3 in 1 million) for the vaccinated student.
These risks are too small to protect
students against themselves. By contrast, the chance of dying in a car crash is
0.01% each year. Yet, universities
do not, and should not, push college students to cut their driving way down in
order to reduce their chance of death. A safety proponent might argue that it
is better for a college student to drive than to be unvaccinated because while
the expected cost of being unvaccinated is smaller than the cost of cutting
driving way down, the benefit of driving is much larger. That is, driving is a
better decision – understood in terms of costs and benefits – than being
unvaccinated. Perhaps so.
Still, we should allow
people to make imprudent decisions. On average, it is imprudent for an adult to
be obese, drop out of high school, have children out of wedlock, or smoke. At
non-elite universities, some majors are poor investments, financially and
intellectually. Consider, for example, art, education, social work, and theater. Yet we allow adults
to major in these subjects. In fact, we subsidize their doing so.
Second, consider whether we should
protect college students in order to protect them from harming others. Let us
assume that the chance of an unvaccinated college student getting Covid is 1 in 3. The chance of a
Covid positive student passing it onto another person is hard to estimate. Let
us assume that the student shares a household with a vaccinated 65-year-old,
the vaccinated 65-year-old has an infection fatality
rate
of 0.14% (1.4 in a 1,000) and
there is a 20% chance the
college student will transmit it if he is Covid positive. The unvaccinated college
student has increased the 65-year-old’s chance of death by 0.009% (very roughly,
1 in 10,000). Is this enough risk to require someone get a medical treatment he
desperately doesn’t want? Without a general argument, we can’t answer this
question. If we can’t answer it, the default position should be against the
requirement because, other things being equal, less regulation of our lives is
better.
By analogy, if
each gun owner were to increase another’s chance of death by 1 in 10,000 –
whether by accident, murder, or suicide - this intuitively does not seem high
enough to justify taking guns away. The cost-benefit analysis might differ here
because people get more out of owning guns than being unvaccinated. More
importantly, though, there is something odd about government requiring us to do
things on the basis of an economic consideration, at least when it involves our
body, and the odds of harm are very small. We do not want the government
prohibiting alcohol, fast food, guns, or SUVs, even if it were efficient to do
so. We do not want the government requiring poor women who get welfare benefits
- for example, cash, food, medicine, or housing - to have to get birth control
shots because it is efficient to require that they do so. If divorce, obesity, and transgenderism were contagious –
evidence suggests they are – we still do not want such individuals banned from campuses,
pressured, or taxed in order to slow the spread of these things. This is true
even if such policies are efficient. Perhaps these requirements infringe
fundamental rights and Covid vaccine shots do not. Again, though, we need an
argument as to why this is so.
There is also the
issue of whom we are trying to protect. We might be trying to protect the
unvaccinated. However, they assumed the risk and it is hard to see why they
deserve protection. We might be trying to protect the vaccinated. This raises
the issue of whether there are enough unvaccinated people who have not had
Covid and whether the threat these people pose is serious enough to justify the
vaccine mandate. If the threat they pose is an additional 1 in 10,000 in chance
of death by Covid, this looks similar to the gun-ownership case.
An objector might
argue that the vaccine mandate is an offer rather than a threat. He might claim
that no one has a right to attend college and so in return for the benefit of
doing so, the college may require students do certain things. Universities may
require a student pass most of his classes, pay tuition, and not walk around
naked. The claim is that the vaccine mandate is like these requirements.
One problem with
this objection is that if the offer-not-a-threat argument were to succeed, the
college could also require students be celibate, refrain from drinking, or stay
thin and attractive. That is, there is no stopping point to this argument.
Intuitively, universities may not require students or faculty waive fundamental
rights - consider those related to free
speech, religion, and search and seizure - in return for attending the university.
If the right against being vaccinated is a fundamental right, and this is
unclear, the mandate would be similarly problematic.
No comments:
Post a Comment