Stephen
Kershnar
The Case for Sex Discrimination in
Academia
Dunkirk-Fredonia Observer
October
30, 2017
The
academic world is very busy trying to hire women and minorities. A good illustration
of this is what is going on in philosophy.
Philosophers
are putting an enormous amount of resources into increasing the number of women
in the profession. Women are favored in hiring in philosophy. There are philosophy
summer programs open to women and minorities, but not white males, that help
them prepare for graduate school. There are quotas for keynote speakers,
women-only scholarships, and close attention paid to the percentage of women in
the profession. Much of this is also true in other fields such as those in science,
technology, engineering, and math (STEM).
Whatever
justifies the state paying for universities also justifies merit-based hiring. This
is because more of the good things that universities bring about (for example,
education or research) will come about if universities hire the best person for
the job. The case for producing more of these good things is especially
compelling at state universities given that the state makes taxpayers pay professors’
salaries and overhead.
In
philosophy, merit-based hiring favors discrimination in favor of men. Male
philosophers produce more research than do female philosophers. This is true in
general and in the top journals in the field. This is probably not the result
of discrimination by the reviewers (the field’s gatekeepers) because the greater
the degree of anonymous review, the greater the disparity. The publication
difference is consistent with the clear majority of the most influential
philosophers being men.
The
case for discrimination rests in part on the failure of studies to show that
women are better researchers in other ways or better teachers. Male professors
get better teaching evaluations, although some researchers do not think this is
due to their being better in the classroom. Women do more service (for example,
committee work), but, generally, universities do not think service is as
important as research and teaching.
The
result fits into a general pattern. For example, while female medical
professors acquire federal funding at similar rate to male professors, they
publish less and their publications have less impact. In science, generally,
women publish less.
This
case for discrimination should not be surprising. There are a number of cases
when gender or race discrimination for limited state positions is appealing.
Currently, there is a shortage of physicians. 25% of female physicians in the
U.S. do not work full-time. Discounting female applications by the likelihood
they leave the field would decrease this shortage. Another instance of this is
discounting minority applications to medical school. The cost of medical error
is high and there is good reason to believe that black and Hispanic doctors, specifically
those who strongly benefit from affirmative action, commit more errors and more
serious errors.
Perhaps
female philosophers are less productive because they are more likely than men to
work part-time rather than full-time in philosophy. While there is no data in
support of this, it is true in other fields (for example, physicians and
veterinarians). In the absence of evidence that fewer female philosophers work
full-time or that when they do work full-time they work fewer hours, this is
not a reason to discriminate against them.
One objector might claim that
research, even at elite universities, is not important and, hence, universities
should not discriminate on the basis of research. If this were true, then the
way in which professors are hired, promoted, and paid is largely mistaken. This
objection succeeds, then, only by throwing out what faculty currently look at when
hiring and promoting philosophers.
A second objector might focus on the
cost of sex discrimination. She might argue that women in philosophy are particularly valuable because
they provide role models, reduce
stereotypes, improve group decision-making,
make the workplace less homogenous, and provide other benefits (for example, more
investment into women’s education). Even if this were true, though, it is unclear
that these benefits outweigh the cost in research productivity. In the absence
of knowledge of the balance of these benefits and costs, discriminating against
women is reasonable. The same is true for not discriminating.
A third objection
is that women’s lesser productivity in philosophy is due to injustice. Perhaps
unequal and unfair demands on mothers or workplace hostility explains the difference.
The problem with this objection is that, if true, it might justify changing the
workplace. It is less clear that it justifies giving women positions for which
they are, on average, less meritorious. If one NFL running back is better than
a second, most people (including the owner, coaches, players, and fans) think
the first should be hired over the second even if injustice caused the second
to be worse. It is unclear why it is more important to choose the best running
back than the best philosopher.
A
fourth objection is that merit-based hiring should be done on an
application-by-application basis. The objector argues that an employer should not
favor someone merely because he is a man. This objection does not succeed if a
person’s sex helps us predict how well someone will perform. Based on what we
know about research production in philosophy, medicine, and STEM and what we
know about career choices and performance elsewhere, it is reasonable to
believe that sex adds to what we know about an applicant’s likely performance
in the future.
Universities
regularly use other rough predictive information such as how elite the school
was from which an applicant graduated, how well she does when interviewed, and number
and quality of publications. There should not be a much higher bar for sex-based
predictive factors than other predictive factors. Also, this objection will not
work for affirmative-action proponents because they support taking sex and race
into account.
In
philosophy and likely much of the academic world, state universities should
either not discriminate or, if they must discriminate, they should favor
men.
No comments:
Post a Comment